De Ethica https://de-ethica.com/ <p><em>De Ethica - A Journal of Philosophical, Theological, and Applied Ethics</em></p> <p><em>De Ethica</em> seeks to publish scholarly works in philosophical, theological, and applied ethics.</p> Linköping University Electronic Press en-US De Ethica 2001-8819 From the Editors https://de-ethica.com/article/view/5043 Lars Lindblom Copyright (c) 2023 Lars Lindblom https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0 2023-10-27 2023-10-27 7 4 1 1 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.23731 From the Guest Editors https://de-ethica.com/article/view/5042 Michael Coors Lea Chilian Copyright (c) 2023 Michael Coors, Lea Chilian https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0 2023-10-27 2023-10-27 7 4 2 6 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.23732 From the Editors https://de-ethica.com/article/view/5041 Lars Lindblom Per Sundman Copyright (c) 2023 Lars Lindblom, Per Sundman https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0 2023-12-15 2023-12-15 7 4 1 2 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.23741 Portraiture and Anthropocentrism https://de-ethica.com/article/view/4744 <p class="Abstract"><span lang="EN-GB">In an age in which anthropocentrism is increasingly under fire, the investment of the artistic tradition in that paradigm deserves particular attention. Portraiture is especially significant, as it seems to be the anthropocentric art form par excellence. It seems to reinforce key features of anthropocentrism: the distinction of the human from the nonhuman and the superiority of the former over the latter. We can pursue these questions most effectively if we distinguish descriptive (“weak”) anthropocentrism from normative (“strong”) anthropocentrism. The former involves some sort of focus on humans, the latter combines this with claims about their superiority over the nonhuman. Certain works by influential portraitists, such as Pablo Picasso, Frida Kahlo, and Ana Mendieta, contest both weak and strong anthropocentrism. Other portraits seem to be involved in weak anthropocentrism, but not necessarily strong anthropocentrism. Considering the artwork of Alice Neel and the philosophy of Judith Butler, I argue that such works have an important ethical role to play in orienting us in our relationships with humans, precisely in resisting strong anthropocentrism even in expressing weak anthropocentrism.</span></p> Stephen Bush Copyright (c) 2023 Stephen Bush https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0 2023-10-27 2023-10-27 7 4 93 107 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.237393 Vulnerable Integrity https://de-ethica.com/article/view/4735 <p>This paper presents a social-theologically informed interpretation of the term integrity, as it occurs in fundamental law. It explores the manifestations of integrity violations and proceeds to draw an inference: an integrity violation can directly emanate from a misconception regarding integrity itself, as well as the implementation of protective measures that follow it. Integrity in its wholeness dimension is understood as open-endedness and non-seclusion rather than as a substantial, clearly definable characteristic of a person. This open-endedness and non-seclusion results from the relational constitution of an individual. Consequently, it follows that a violation of integrity occurs when the open-endedness and non-seclusion of a person and their relational Becoming is hindered. The new definition of integrity is particularly important when it comes to the governance of new health technologies, especially Digital Twins that can become representatives of a person. Human integrity is non-violated only when it is understood as open to relational Becoming and this Becoming shows its expression in the mutual enabling and support of self-articulation.</p> Tabea Ott Peter Dabrock Copyright (c) 2023 Tabea Ott, Peter Dabrock https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0 2023-10-27 2023-10-27 7 4 47 60 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.237347 Vulnerability in Times of War https://de-ethica.com/article/view/4721 <p>Vulnerability as a critique of the one-sidedness of the principle of autonomy is at risk of overemphasizing the positive dimension of vulnerability. Moreover, in the discourse on vulnerability, the threat of dehumanization (or moral vulnerability) has not been scrutinized enough ethically. Therefore, the ethics of vulnerability is insufficient when faced with the force of war that requires the conceptualization of vulnerability for political-ethics. The Russian war in Ukraine demonstrates this weakness in a striking way: the called-for openness to the other as well as an active form of nonviolence, as promoted by Judith Butler, may not be an option in times of war. Continuing Jessica Benjamin’s psychoanalytic approach to mutual recognition, the essay shows that the task of morality does not rest upon broadening one’s vulnerability, but rather in understanding vulnerable agency as the dialectic of vulnerability and agency. For the further development of this dialectic, the triadic figuration is emphasized, complementing the dyadic relation of self and other. While the Third can take multiple figurations in the psychoanalytical setting, I understand the Third within the political-ethical context as the possibility of a “moral world” of nonviolence and respect. During war, the role of the bystander is to become a witness who, through the process of witnessing, advocacy, diplomacy, and justice, allows for the moral Third to reemerge. Among others, the ethics of vulnerability must spell out the price for the failure of taking on this responsibility, namely the eclipse of morality.</p> Hille Haker Copyright (c) 2023 Hille Haker https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0 2023-11-23 2023-11-23 7 4 7 29 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.23737 Self-determined Sex Work as Care Work Between Experiences of Integrity and Vulnerability https://de-ethica.com/article/view/4688 <p>Sex work or prostitution marks a controversial topic for Protestant sexual ethics. It is also a multifaceted phenomenon because it can occur in very different forms: the spectrum ranges from poverty, emergency and procurement prostitution to the self-determined and insured sex worker with all imaginable shades in between. In the current economic system, goods and services are exchanged, traded, sold, acquired and paid for, so sex work can also be understood as work. For the purposes of this article, we will therefore start from an understanding of sex work as care work. Care work can be understood as the satisfaction of needs and interests of third parties and the self. If sex work is discussed as care work, this has a variety of consequences. These include the fact that questions of vulnerability and integrity come to the fore. Integrity can be comprehended as self-realisation or autonomy and thus as potentially vulnerable, taking up Axel Honneth’s early reflections on the issue of recognition. Integrity in Axel Honneth’s sense can - according to a first approximation - play a role for sex work on three levels: physical or corporeal level, structural level and lifestyle or way of life level. Finally, the essay discusses the concept of negotiated or consensual morality as a contribution of Protestant ethics.</p> Sarah Jäger Copyright (c) 2023 Sarah Jäger https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0 2023-10-27 2023-10-27 7 4 61 74 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.237361 From the Editors https://de-ethica.com/article/view/4628 Lars Lindblom Erik Gustavsson Copyright (c) 2023 Lars Lindblom; Erik Gustavsson https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0 2023-03-27 2023-03-27 7 4 1 2 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.23721 Helping Refugees Build a Home https://de-ethica.com/article/view/4552 <p>This study focuses on the question of how Muslim chaplains can, through their interventions, exert an influence on the situation of refugees, characterised by vulnerability and loss of home. Based on definitions in social work and anthropology studies, home can be conceptualised as a key anthropological need, comprised of spatial, temporal, relational and spiritual dimensions. Referring to an empirical study on asylum chaplaincy in Switzerland, this study analyses how five Muslim chaplains accompany refugees, how their styles of chaplaincy differ in practice and what effects their interventions have. These empirical results are then brought into conversation with a theoretical framework, to explore the connections between counselling and vulnerability. While it could be argued that referring to the vulnerable situation of refugees reinforces an image of passivity, the co-construction of a home represents a collaborative effort and empowers refugees by mobilising both forces and resources. Chaplains, in particular, can contribute to the relational and spiritual dimensions of home. For refugees, articulating their religious concerns and working together with Muslim chaplains, means they can address the limits of the existing asylum system and demand recognition of cultural diversity.</p> Hansjörg Schmid Copyright (c) 2023 Hansjörg Schmid https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0 2023-10-27 2023-10-27 7 4 75 92 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.237375 Integrity, Vulnerability, and Temporality https://de-ethica.com/article/view/4532 <p>This paper asks how to account for vulnerable integrity in the temporal dynamism of human lives without relying on a subtractive vision of integral human nature, borrowing from presumed past or future rationality and maturity, or depending on an external attribution of dignity. Illustrating the challenges with vignettes from the author’s life, it argues inductively that human integrity includes morally inviolable vulnerability to others with whom we are in interdependent relationship and without whom we cannot develop or maintain our selves. Others reside at the core of our integrity, for better and for worse, and we reside at theirs. Augustine’s accounts of memory, time, and the narrative self; Whiteheadian process thought’s understanding of continuity through change; and feminist theories of narrative all provide theological and philosophical justifications for this vision of integrity. John Wall’s and Johan Brännmark’s non-foundational approaches to integrity and human rights lead us to the same conclusion without entailing theological anthropological claims, ensuring its relevance in a pluralist culture.</p> Cristina Traina Copyright (c) 2023 Cristina Traina https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0 2023-10-27 2023-10-27 7 4 30 46 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.237330 Epicurean Priority-setting During the COVID-19 Pandemic and Beyond https://de-ethica.com/article/view/4403 <div> <p class="Abstract"><span lang="EN-GB">The aim of this article is to study the relationship between Epicureanism and pandemic priority-setting and to explore whether Epicurus's philosophy is compliant with the later developed utilitarianism. We find this aim interesting because Epicurus had a different way of valuing death than our modern society does: Epicureanism holds that death—understood as the incident of death—cannot be bad (or good) for those who die (self-regarding effects). However, this account is still consistent with the view that a particular death can be bad for everyone else but those who die, such as family, friends, and society (other-regarding effects). During the pandemic, the focus has been on the number of deaths more than on the suffering and reduced well-being of those infected and the rest of society. However, since the pandemic requires prioritization, it is, on a utilitarian account, important to consider priorities that do the most good overall. In this article, we approach the harm of death from an Epicurean point of view, seeking to flesh out potential implications for pandemic priority-setting, and healthcare in general, using a case study of COVID-19 priority-setting. We also explore whether this would conflict with utilitarianism. We conclude that an Epicurean pandemic priority-setting approach would be different but, surprisingly, not radically different from many of the actual priority-setting decisions we saw under the COVID-19 pandemic.</span></p> </div> Bjørn Hol Carl Tollef Solberg Copyright (c) 2023 Bjørn Hol, Carl Tollef Solberg https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0 2023-03-29 2023-03-29 7 4 63 83 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.237263 The Problem with Using a Maxim Permissibility Test to Derive Obligations https://de-ethica.com/article/view/4363 <div> <p class="Abstract"><span lang="EN-US">The purpose of this paper is to show that, if Kant’s universalization formulations of the Categorical Imperative are our only standards for judging right from wrong and permissible from impermissible, then we have no obligations. I shall do this by examining five different views of how obligations can be derived from the universalization formulations and arguing that each one fails. I shall argue that the first view rests on a misunderstanding of the universalization formulations; the second on a misunderstanding of the concept of an obligation; the third on a misunderstanding of the concept of a maxim; the fourth on a misunderstanding of the limits of action description; and the fifth on a misunderstanding of the universalization formulations again.</span></p> </div> Samuel Kahn Copyright (c) 2022 Samuel Kahn https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0 2022-06-23 2022-06-23 7 4 31 40 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.227131 From the Editors https://de-ethica.com/article/view/4362 Lars Lindblom Elena Namli Copyright (c) 2022 Lars Lindblom; Elena Namli https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0 2022-06-23 2022-06-23 7 4 1 2 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.22711 Another Pandemic https://de-ethica.com/article/view/4357 <div> <p><span lang="EN-US">The SARS-CoV-2 pandemic has transgressed biomedical categories. According to Horton, it turned out to be a 'syndrome' that infected virtually all spheres of social life. The pandemic has created toxic social atmosphere highly unfavorable to clinical and clinic-ethical decision making. Constraints and pressures related to micro-, meso-, exo- and macro-environments framing doctors, nurses, and medical students in training were identified. These factors exacerbated moral distress (moral injury) amongst clinicians. In a joint Polish-Lithuanian project (IDUB 2020-2022) we examined predictors of moral distress in pandemic clinical contexts. A survey-based, real-time, correlational and comparative study was conducted in Poland and Lithuania after the first year of pandemic with <em>N=227</em> participants. Unexpected differences on regular and pandemic-type moral distress levels were found between the two national</span> <span lang="EN-US">samples. Polish participants showed significantly higher moral distress levels than their Lithuanian counterparts. The following article discusses these findings and recommends the reinforcement of resilient medical decision making. &nbsp;&nbsp;</span></p> </div> Ewa Nowak Anna-Maria Barciszewska Roma Kriaučiūnienė Agnė Jakavonytė-Akstinienė Karolina Napiwodzka Paweł Mazur Marina Klimenko Clara Owen Copyright (c) 2023 Nowak, Barciszewska, Kriaučiūnienė, Jakavonytė-Akstinienė, Napiwodzka, Mazur, Klimenko , Owen https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0 2023-04-17 2023-04-17 7 4 3 27 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.23723 Being Claimed in Immediate Response to an Other https://de-ethica.com/article/view/4355 <div class="page" title="Page 5"> <div class="layoutArea"> <div class="column"> <p>In this essay, I propose a phenomenological alternative to the established candidates of what grounds moral status, namely the experience of being claimed in immediate response to an Other. Drawing from late-Wittgensteinian moral philosophy, I develop this alternative in critical juxtaposition to theories that aim to derive moral status from values grounded in independently accountable empirical properties. Against such theories, I expound how meaningful talk of moral status must instead be understood to be rooted in the individuals’ morally charged immediate responsiveness to Others, a responsiveness that preconditions the very possibility of separating value and fact. If my analysis is sound, then the empirical property or set of properties that is commonly taken to qualify as a candidate for a ground of moral status in fact presupposes a phenomenological dimension of ‘ethical encounter’. The recognition of this deeper phenomenological level would, while not disposing with the notion of moral status, transform its meaning and, thus, how much of the philosophical debate on moral status is conducted.</p> </div> </div> </div> Philip Strammer Copyright (c) 2023 Philip Strammer https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0 2023-12-15 2023-12-15 7 4 3 15 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.23743 The Grounding Problem of Equal Respect https://de-ethica.com/article/view/4353 <div class="page" title="Page 38"> <div class="layoutArea"> <div class="column"> <p>In this paper, I explore three theories of value to illuminate how nontheistic and theistic accounts may differ in grounding human dignity: neo- Aristotelian ethical naturalism, Kantian constructivism, and a theistic account of good simpliciter. The theistic account of good simpliciter that I offer adapts Robert Adams’s notion of the transcendent Good as the Excellent. In this account, I explain how Adams’ thesis that goodness is a property consisting in a sort of resemblance to God may be understood in a new way, using ideas drawn from contemporary mathematics and quantum mechanics. On my account, we must value human beings neither because such valuing would be beneficial or necessary for human flourishing nor because it is a logical outcome of anything we care to value. Rather it is because we recognize the property of self-similarity in all of us, which may be understood as a resemblance to God as good simpliciter.</p> </div> </div> </div> Kevin Jung Copyright (c) 2023 Kevin Jung https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0 2023-12-15 2023-12-15 7 4 35 49 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.237435 In defense of a ‘thick’ formal equality principle in healthcare resource distribution https://de-ethica.com/article/view/4345 <div class="page" title="Page 53"> <div class="layoutArea"> <div class="column"> <p>Given resource constraints in healthcare, demands justice and equity require the constant development of material principles for resource distribution. In many cases, such material principles are formulated as mid-level principles, well-adapted to handle healthcare distribution but suffering from aspects outside the healthcare context that affect their application. In healthcare, factors outside the healthcare system will sometimes affect patients’ equal opportunity to receive treatment and achieve health. Examples of such factors might include an individual’s economic means, the cost of drugs, geography, etc. This article explores whether the formal equality principle could help us address such problems. It is argued that the traditional (thin) formal equality principle can aid in priority setting, both as a heuristic tool to aid in consistency and also in handling under-determined cases. However, it appears to be too ‘thin’ to handle problems caused by factors outside the healthcare context. In the article, I explore a more robust version of the formal equality principle and argue that such a principle can be used to address such cases. However, even a more comprehensive formal equality principle will need to consider whether some other actors have a moral responsibility to address the problem or whether the issue could be solved more effectively by others. Furthermore, such a principle needs to consider whether the opportunity cost of achieving ‘thick’ formal equality is acceptable, given the material principles of distribution.</p> </div> </div> </div> Lars Sandman Copyright (c) 2023 Lars Sandman https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0 2023-12-15 2023-12-15 7 4 50 67 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.237450 Ectogenesis and the Moral Status of the Fetus https://de-ethica.com/article/view/4332 <p>Many people believe the morality of abortion stands or falls with the moral status of the fetus.&nbsp; Judith Jarvis Thomson’s violinist argument bypasses the question of fetal moral status; even if the fetus has a right to life, she argues the gestational mother has a right to disconnect herself from the fetus. However, should <em>ectogenesis</em> – a technology that would allow the fetus to develop outside the womb – become sufficiently advanced, the fetus would no longer need a gestational mother to live.&nbsp; Recently, Joona Räsänen has argued that parents have a right to secure the death of a fetus that has been removed from the mother’s body, and that this right might extend to infanticide. &nbsp;However, here I argue Räsänen’s position ignores the moral status of the fetus; if the fetus is morally comparable to beings like us, then of course parents lack a right to the death of their children.&nbsp; However, if the fetus is morally comparable to a tumor, then the right to kill it is philosophically uninteresting.</p> <p>&nbsp;</p> William Simkulet Copyright (c) 2022 William Simkulet https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0 2022-06-23 2022-06-23 7 4 3 18 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.22713 Grounding Basic Equality https://de-ethica.com/article/view/4181 <div class="page" title="Page 18"> <div class="layoutArea"> <div class="column"> <p>Although egalitarianism has been the dominant orthodoxy in Anglophone social and political philosophy for many decades, there have been surprisingly few attempts to account for the axiom on which it rests, namely that human moral worth does not come in degrees. This article begins by rehearsing and evaluating two families of approaches to the grounding problem. The first favours accounts that seek to preserve consistency with metaphysical naturalism, while the second relies on more philosophically contentious claims about the metaphysical status of the human person. I then outline reasons for supposing that none of these accounts of basic equality offers a convincing theoretical foundation for egalitarianism. I conclude by sketching permutations of a theological account before arguing that one of these variations satisfies many of the explanatory criteria that a successful solution requires.</p> </div> </div> </div> James Orr Copyright (c) 2023 James Orr https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0 2023-12-15 2023-12-15 7 4 16 34 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.237416 Ethical Obligations of Global Justice in the Midst of Global Pandemics https://de-ethica.com/article/view/4166 <p><span style="font-weight: 400;">This paper considers the obligation higher income countries have to lower and middle income countries during a global pandemic. Further considers which reforms are needed to the global supply-chain of medical resources. The short-comings in distribution and medical infrastructure have exacerbated the health crisis in developing countries. Global justice demands radical redistribution of medical resources in order to prevent mass casualties. This is argued first by highlighting that the COVID-19 pandemic should be acknowledged as an issue of global justice, secondly, higher income countries ought to account for distribution inequity as a matter of rectifying past injustices, and thirdly argue for reform in distribution while considering the vaccine rollout as a prime example. We aim to show how the differences from country to country in response capabilities are a result of the economic foundation colonialism established and a direct result of cyclical poverty, which wealthy countries perpetuate to this day.</span></p> Sarah Hicks Paula Gurtler Copyright (c) 2023 Sarah Hicks, Paula Gurtler https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0 2023-03-29 2023-03-29 7 4 44 62 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.237244 Reciprocity as an Argument for Prioritizing Health Care Workers for the COVID-19 Vaccine https://de-ethica.com/article/view/4159 <p>During the recent debates on whether to prioritize health care workers for COVID-19 vaccines, two main lines of arguments emerged: one centered on maximizing health and one centered on reciprocity. In this article, we scrutinize the argument from reciprocity. The notions of fittingness and proportionality are fundamental for the act of reciprocating. We consider the importance of these notions for various arguments from reciprocity, showing that the arguments are problematic. If there is a plausible argument for reciprocity during the pandemic, this is most likely one that centers on the risk that health care workers take on while working. We argue that the scope of this argument is not plausibly extended only to health care workers. Other essential workers at risk are in the position to make the same arguments. We also argue that there is no compelling argument from reciprocity that makes reciprocating with vaccines, rather than by other means, necessary. Furthermore, allocating vaccines based on reciprocity will conflict with utility-maximizing. Given the weak state of the arguments, overriding concerns for utility seem unreasonable.&nbsp;</p> Borgar Jølstad Carl Tollef Solberg Copyright (c) 2023 Mr., Dr. https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0 2023-04-01 2023-04-01 7 4 28 43 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.237228 From Ethical Analysis to Legal Reform https://de-ethica.com/article/view/3925 <div> <p class="AbstractCxSpFirst"><span lang="EN-US">Ethical analysis may result in recommendations for legal reform. This article discusses the problem of how academic researchers can go from ethical normative judgments to recommendations for law reform. It develops a methodological framework for what may be called ‘ethical transplants’: transplanting ethical normative judgments into legislation. It is an inventory of the issues that need to be addressed, but not a substantive normative theory. It may be especially helpful for Ph.D. students and beginning researchers working in interdisciplinary projects combining ethical and legal analysis.<br /></span><span style="font-size: 0.875rem;">I distinguish three stages in the process from ethics to law: translation, transformation, and incorporation. The latter stage can be divided into three clusters of issues, these being legal, empirical, and normative ones. Most of the philosophical literature on the legal enforcement of morals focuses on the normative issues. My aim is to broaden the perspective in two ways. First, I show that this is only one relevant issue and that we should address legal and empirical issues and the processes of translation and transformation as well. Second, I argue that we should pay more attention to pluralism and variation.</span></p> </div> Wibren van der Burg Copyright (c) 2022 Wibren van der Burg https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0 2022-06-23 2022-06-23 7 4 41 59 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.227141 Does Libertarian Self-Ownership Protect Freedom? https://de-ethica.com/article/view/3891 <div> <p class="Abstract"><span lang="EN-GB">Many libertarians assume that there is a close relation between an individual’s self-ownership and her freedom. That relation needs questioning. In this article it is argued that, even in a pre-property state, self-ownership is insufficient to protect freedom. Therefore, libertarians who believe in self-ownership should either offer a defense of freedom that is independent from their defense of self-ownership, make it explicit that they hold freedom as second to self-ownership (and defend that position), or reconsider the moral basis of their political views.</span></p> </div> Jesper Ahlin Marceta Copyright (c) 2022 Jesper Ahlin Marceta https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0 2022-06-23 2022-06-23 7 4 19 30 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.227119 On Some Moral Implications of Linguistic Narrativism Theory https://de-ethica.com/article/view/3120 <p>In this essay we consider the moral claims of one branch of non-realist theory known as linguistic narrativism theory. By highlighting the moral implications of linguistic narrativism theory, we argue that the “moral vision” expressed by this theory can entail, at worst, undesirable moral agnosticism if not related to a transcendental and supra-personal normativity in our moral life. With its appeal to volitionism and intuitionism, the ethical sensitivity of this theory enters into difficulties brought about by several internal tensions as to what morality and moral judgements involve. We contend that the proponents of linguistic narrativism theory must strongly recognize and take responsibility for the “moral vison” their theory professes, in so far as they want to think of their theory as a morally responsible one.</p> Natan Elgabsi Bennett Gilbert Copyright (c) 2020 Natan Elgabsi, Bennett Gilbert https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0 2020-06-30 2020-06-30 7 4 75 91 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.206175 ‘What Do We Do with the Art of Monstrous Men?’ Betrayal and the Feminist Ethics of Aesthetic Involvement https://de-ethica.com/article/view/3119 <p>The #MeToo movement has put a spotlight on sexual harassment and abuse in a number of industries, notably the arts. It has raised a set of questions about how to receive the artistic works of the accused, particularly when such work has been beloved or formative for an individual, and collectively when it has cultural significance and influence. Claire Dederer, writing in The Paris Review, posed the question bluntly in her piece, “What Do We Do with the Art of Monstrous Men?” This question, and the range of (often perplexed) responses to it, reveal the lack of adequate resources to evaluate responses to an artist’s actions that may bear on our aesthetic valuations of the artist’s work and that may be experienced as quite intimately personal. What do we do with the sense of betrayal that may follow on the discovery of an artist’s bad behavior? What are the implications of consuming of such art? What concepts and norms might help to guide reflection? These questions bear on the ethical significance of love and appreciation for artworks and artists, and, more broadly, the ethical consumption of artworks. This paper responds to these questions in two ways: first, it develops an account of “aesthetic involvement” to elaborate the sense of betrayal that may follow accusations or revelations of sexual harassment and abuse. Second, it proposes a feminist ethics of aesthetic involvement in response to such betrayals and to dilemmas about the individual and collective ethical consumption of artworks.</p> Sarah Stewart-Kroeker Copyright (c) 2020 Sarah Stewart-Kroeker https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0 2020-06-30 2020-06-30 7 4 51 74 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.19062502 Distributive Energy Justice and the Common Good https://de-ethica.com/article/view/3118 <p>Recently, philosophers and social scientists have shown increased interest in questions of social, global, and intergenerational distributive justice related to energy production and consumption. However, so far there have been only a few attempts to analyse questions of distributive energy justice from a religious point of view, which should be considered a lack since religions are an important basis of morality for a large part of the world’s population. In this article, I analyse issues of distributive energy justice from a Christian theological viewpoint by employing the Catholic common good tradition as a theoretical framework. First, I present and argue for a global and ecological interpretation of the Catholic common good tradition. Then I analyse the implications of such an interpretation on questions of distributive energy justice, focusing on the view of property rights within the Catholic common good tradition. I conclude that, in comparison with Nussbaum’s liberal capabilities approach, the common good tradition provides stronger reasons for individuals and groups in more economically developed countries to share their resources and knowledge with individuals and groups in less economically developed countries.</p> Anders Melin Copyright (c) 2020 Anders Melin https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0 2020-06-30 2020-06-30 7 4 35 50 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.19062501 Violence, Shame, and Moral Agency – An Exploration of Krista K. Thomason’s Position https://de-ethica.com/article/view/3117 <p>Krista Thomason’s account of shame explains the link between shame and violence as something that arises out of a tension between our identity and our self-conception: those things about which we feel shame are part of our identities, but they are not part of our self-conception. She sees violence as an attempt to regain agency and control and overcome shame. Although this is an important trait in shame, to explain violence as a response to the loss of agency is not sufficient. Furthermore, it cannot explain serious self-harm as the result of shame, since such reactions undermined the agency she holds that violence attempts to reclaim. Hence, these features need to be incorporated into a wider account of shame that sees it as a response to the interruption of intentional projects and attempts for coherent agency.</p> Jan-Olav Henriksen Copyright (c) 2020 Jan-Olav Henriksen https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0 2020-06-30 2020-06-30 7 4 23 34 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.206123 Moral agency without responsibility? Analysis of three ethical models of human-computer interaction in times of artificial intelligence (AI) https://de-ethica.com/article/view/3116 <p>Philosophical and sociological approaches in technology have increasingly shifted toward describing AI (artificial intelligence) systems as ‘(moral) agents,’ while also attributing ‘agency’ to them. It is only in this way – so their principal argument goes – that the effects of technological components in a complex human-computer interaction can be understood sufficiently in phenomenological-descriptive and ethical-normative respects. By contrast, this article aims to demonstrate that an explanatory model only achieves a descriptively and normatively satisfactory result if the concepts of ‘(moral) agent’ and ‘(moral) agency’ are exclusively related to human agents. Initially, the division between symbolic and sub-symbolic AI, the black box character of (deep) machine learning, and the complex relationship network in the provision and application of machine learning are outlined. Next, the ontological and action-theoretical basic assumptions of an ‘agency’ attribution regarding both the current teleology-naturalism debate and the explanatory model of actor network theory are examined. On this basis, the technical-philosophical approaches of Luciano Floridi, Deborah G. Johnson, and Peter-Paul Verbeek will all be critically discussed. Despite their different approaches, they tend to fully integrate computational behavior into their concept of ‘(moral) agency.’ By contrast, this essay recommends distinguishing conceptually between the different entities, causalities, and relationships in a human-computer interaction, arguing that this is the only way to do justice to both human responsibility and the moral significance and causality of computational behavior.</p> Alexis Fritz Wiebke Brandt Henner Gimpel Sarah Bayer Copyright (c) 2020 Alexis Fritz, Wiebke Brandt, Henner Gimpel, Sarah Bayer https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0 2020-06-30 2020-06-30 7 4 3 22 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.20613 From the Editors https://de-ethica.com/article/view/3115 <p>No abstract available.</p> Elena Namli Copyright (c) 2020 Elena Namli https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0 2020-06-30 2020-06-30 7 4 1 2 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.20611 From the Editors: De Ethica. A Journal of Philosophical, Theological and Applied Ethics https://de-ethica.com/article/view/1791 <p>No abstract available.</p> Jenny Ehnberg Copyright (c) 2018 Ehnberg https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0 2018-05-07 2018-05-07 7 4 1 2 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.18511 Evil as a Distortion of Communication: On Hegel’s account of Evil as Subjectivism https://de-ethica.com/article/view/1792 The early Hegel’s conception of evil draws on a very different paradigm than the current philosophical discourse on evil and therefore challenges received assumptions and can give us fresh impulses. In this paper, I first present Hegel’s conception of evil through a close reading of the Jenaer Realphilosophie’s, prima facie, obscure claim that evil is the ’internal actual, absolute certainty of itself, the pure night of being for itself‘. Hegel discusses evil because he worries how Romanticism and the romantic ideal of authenticity impact the possibility of communication. I then develop the idea that evil is a distortion of communication. I argue that this account of evil helps us to distinguish between evil and mere moral badness. Finally, I address two problems for this account, and discuss its limits. Martin Sticker Copyright (c) 2018 Sticker https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0 2018-05-07 2018-05-07 7 4 3 20 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.18513 On the Relevance of the Concept of Intrinsic Evil: Francisco Suárez and Contemporary Catholic Virtue Ethics Approaches https://de-ethica.com/article/view/1793 The article explores the relevancy of the concept of intrinsic evil/intrinsically evil acts in contemporary Catholic theological ethics as a particular way of giving an account of (moral) evil. The argument proceeds in two steps. In the first step the author turns to Francisco Suárez as one of the first theologians who tried to deal with the concept of intrinsic evil in an extensive and systematic way. The point of this historical exploration is to determine the meanings of this concept as it started to appear more frequently in the ethical discourse. In the next step the author presents two contemporary positions within Catholic theological ethics, those of Joseph Selling and Dana Dillon. Although both authors are proponents of virtue ethics, they disagree fundamentally on the role of the concept of intrinsic evil within this approach. While Joseph Selling argues in favour of eliminating this concept from theological ethics, Dana Dillon posits that theological ethics cannot function without it. In the rest of the article, the author explores this disagreement through various ways in which the concept can be used, while taking into account the aforementioned meanings of the concept. In the end, the author sides with Joseph Selling, since the concept of intrinsic evil does not seem to be able to fulfil the role it was assigned within Catholic theological ethics. Nenad Polgar Copyright (c) 2018 Polgar https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0 2018-05-07 2018-05-07 7 4 21 36 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.185121 Political Decay and Political Arcadianism https://de-ethica.com/article/view/1794 An account of evil in classical political theory is the concept of evil government. The notion of political decay from good to evil government or to anarchy, the absence of government, among classical political theorists represents both a moral and a political problem. This essay argues that political decay remains a perennial problem because the political condition itself involves the seeds to its own destruction. Moreover, it is claimed that the nostalgic longing to a glorious past for nations or peoples risks turning into what is here labelled ‘political arcadianism’, fostering futile attempts to return to past conditions. The argument is that political arcadianism when focusing on the imagined past rather than the present is a possible cause of political decay. Ronnie Hjorth Copyright (c) 2018 Hjorth https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0 2018-05-07 2018-05-07 7 4 37 49 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.185137 Moral Imaginative Resistance to Heaven: Why the Problem of Evil is so Intractable https://de-ethica.com/article/view/1795 The majority of philosophers of religion, at least since Plantinga’s reply to Mackie’s logical problem of evil, agree that it is logically possible for an omnibenevolent, omniscient, and omnipotent God to exist who permits some of the evils we see in the actual world. This is conceivable essentially because of the possible world known as heaven. That is, heaven is an imaginable world in a similar way that logically possible scenarios in any fiction are imaginable. However, like some of the imaginable stories in fiction where we are asked to envision an immoral act as a moral one, we resist. I will employ the works of Tamar Gendler on imaginative resistance and Keith Buhler’s Virtue Ethics approach to moral imaginative resistance and apply them to the conception of heaven and the problem of evil. While we can imagine God as an omnibenevolent parent permitting evil to allow for morally significant freedom and the rewards in heaven or punishments in hell (both possible worlds), we should not. This paper is not intended to be a refutation of particular theodicies; rather it provides a very general groundwork connecting issues of horrendous suffering and imaginative resistance to heaven as a possible world. Chris A. Kramer Copyright (c) 2018 Kramer https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0 2018-05-07 2018-05-07 7 4 51 67 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.185151 From the Editors: De Ethica. A Journal of Philosophical, Theological and Applied Ethics https://de-ethica.com/article/view/1784 <p>Not available.</p> Jenny Ehnberg Copyright (c) 2017 Ehnberg https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0 2017-12-04 2017-12-04 7 4 1 2 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.17431 From the Editors: De Ethica. A Journal of Philosophical, Theological and Applied Ethics https://de-ethica.com/article/view/1785 <p>Not available.</p> Jenny Ehnberg Copyright (c) 2017 Ehnberg https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0 2017-12-04 2017-12-04 7 4 3 5 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.17433 Neutrality, Partiality, and Meaning in Life https://de-ethica.com/article/view/1787 Discussion of whether values and norms are neutral or not has mainly appeared in works on the nature of prudential rationality and morality. Little systematic has yet appeared in the up and coming field of the meaning of life. What are the respects in which the value of meaningfulness is neutral or, in contrast, partial, relational, or ‘biased’? In this article, I focus strictly on answering this question. First, I aim to identify the salient, and perhaps exhaustive, respects in which issues of neutrality arise in the contexts of life’s meaning. In addition to providing a taxonomy of the key points of contention, a second aim is to advance reflection about them by considering the most important arguments that have been marshalled in favour of one side or the other, particularly as they appear in recent neutral positions. I conclude that meaning in life is neutral with respect to time but not any other conditions such as agents and patients, with a third aim being to point out that this makes the value of meaning different from the kinds of non/neutrality encountered in some salient conceptions of prudence and morality. Thaddeus Metz Copyright (c) 2017 Metz https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0 2017-12-04 2017-12-04 7 4 7 26 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.17437 Introduction https://de-ethica.com/article/view/1786 Not available. Frans Svensson Copyright (c) 2017 Svensson https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0 2017-12-04 2017-12-04 7 4 5 6 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.17435 Meaning in Life and the Metaphysics of Value https://de-ethica.com/article/view/1788 According to subjectivist views about a meaningful life, ones life is meaningful in virtue of desire satisfaction or feelings of fulfilment. Standard counterexamples consist of satisfaction found through trivial or immoral tasks. In response to such examples, many philosophers require that the tasks one is devoted to are objectively valuable, or have objectively valuable consequences. I argue that the counterexamples to subjectivism do not require objective value for meaning in life. I also consider other reasons for thinking that meaning in life requires objective value and raise doubts about their strength. Finally, I argue that beauty is not plausibly objective, but that it seems important for meaning. This puts pressure on the objectivist to explain why objectivity matters in the case of other values. Daan Evers Copyright (c) 2017 Evers https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0 2017-12-04 2017-12-04 7 4 27 44 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.174327 A Subjectivist Account of Life’s Meaning https://de-ethica.com/article/view/1789 In this paper, I propose and defend a particular desire-based theory of what makes a person’s life meaningful. Desire-based theories avoid the problems facing other theories of meaning in life: in contrast to objectivist theories (both consequentialist and non-consequentialist ones), they succeed in providing a necessary link between what makes a person’s life meaningful and the person’s own set of attitudes or concerns; in contrast to hybrid theories (or subjectivist theories with a value requirement), they avoid the elitism or exclusivism inherent in the former; and in contrast to mental-state theories, they avoid the problem of not taking the state of the world properly into account when determining whether someone’s life is meaningful. However, meaningfulness does not plausibly depend on the satisfaction of just any desires—perhaps especially not on the satisfaction of desires that we experience as alien to ourselves. I therefore suggest that the meaning in your life depends on the extent to which your categorical desires (i.e. those desires that are partly constitutive of your practical identity) are satisfied or fulfilled. In the final section of the paper, I respond to at least four possible objections to this view. Frans Svensson Copyright (c) 2017 Svensson https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0 2017-12-04 2017-12-04 7 4 45 66 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.174345 What Good is Meaning in Life? https://de-ethica.com/article/view/1790 Most philosophers writing on meaning in life agree that it is a distinct kind of final value. This consensus view has two components: the ‘final value claim’ that meaning in life is a kind of final value, and the ‘distinctness claim’ that it is distinct from all other kinds of final value. This paper discusses some difficulties in vindicating both claims at once. One way to underscore the distinctness of meaning, for example, is to retain a feature of our pre-theoretical concept of meaning in life, according to which the least possible quantity of meaning is meaninglessness. Unfortunately, this makes it harder to defend the claim that meaning is a kind of final value. On the other hand, revising the concept to allow for negative meaning renders meaning closer in structure to other kinds of final value, but also makes it harder to defend the distinctness claim. In light of these difficulties, the paper explores the prospects of a theory of meaning in life which departs from the consensus view by rejecting the final value claim. On such a view, the value of meaning in life is entirely instrumental. Christopher Woodard Copyright (c) 2017 Woodard https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0 2017-12-04 2017-12-04 7 4 67 79 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.17467 From the Editors: De Ethica. A Journal of Philosophical, Theological and Applied Ethics (English) https://de-ethica.com/article/view/1780 <p>No abstract available.</p> Marcus Agnafors Copyright (c) 2017 Agnafors https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0 2017-08-23 2017-08-23 7 4 1 3 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.17421 From the Editors: De Ethica. A Journal of Philosophical, Theological and Applied Ethics (German) https://de-ethica.com/article/view/1781 <p>No abstract available.</p> Marcus Agnafors Copyright (c) 2017 Agnafors https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0 2017-08-23 2017-08-23 7 4 5 8 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.17425 Wage Desert and the Success of Organisations https://de-ethica.com/article/view/1782 People often apply the concept of desert when deciding how to respond to various circumstances and they believe it is appropriate and morally required that they do so. More specifically, desert has long been a prominent (if not the paramount) feature of discussions concerning just compensation. In this essay I argue that providing employees the compensation (remuneration) they deserve – that is, realising wage desert – is essential to demonstrating adequate respect for employees, which, in turn, greatly facilitates the ability of organisations to attract and retain qualified, competent employees and provides employees with a powerful motivation for performing to the best of their ability. In so doing, wage desert offers an effective means for helping to secure and maintain an organisation’s capacity to function as desired and, by extension, be successful. Hence, both for moral and prudential reasons it seems preferable for all involved that the concept of desert be used when determining employee remuneration. Shaun Young Copyright (c) 2017 Young https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0 2017-08-23 2017-08-23 7 4 9 20 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.17429 Unethical Laws and Lawless Ethics: Right and Virtue in Kant’s Rechtslehre https://de-ethica.com/article/view/1783 In this paper, I examine the relation between law and morality within the context of Kant’s late work The Metaphysics of Morals. I argue that Kant’s conception of the law is based on a fundamental distinction between Right and Virtue, which respectively correspond to his legal-political theory and moral philosophy. My analysis is two part: in the first part, I examine the relationship between the Doctrines of Right and Virtue within the Kantian architectonic; in the second, I evaluate two cases of adjudication in the Rechtslehre that exemplify the distinction between law and morality explicated in the preceding section. I begin by showing that Kant’s legal and moral philosophies are normatively distinct, insofar as Right and Virtue belong to incommensurable realms of freedom and necessity. From this distinction, I derive Kant’s conception of the legal state as principally concerned with external freedoms and the preservation of the lawful condition itself. The second part of this paper analyzes Kant’s views on two cases of criminal justice, revealing his prioritization of the political over independent ethical considerations in juridical decision-making. Here, the conceptual barrier between law and morality serves as a caveat against facile recourses to Kantian ethics as means of legitimizing juridico-political decisions. Jenna Zhang Copyright (c) 2017 Zhang https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0 2017-08-23 2017-08-23 7 4 21 34 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.174221 Towards a Legal Turn in the Ethics of Immigration https://de-ethica.com/article/view/1779 This contribution presents the case for a ‘legal turn’ in the ethical debate on immigration. The legal turn is an invitation directed mainly at philosophers to take law as a normative practice seriously, to draw upon the normative resources which it entails and to look for cooperation opportunities with legal scholars. In the continuation of the debates on the ethics of immigration, this legal turn represents an important opportunity for philosophy to gain more relevance in the legal and political realms by affirming its capacity to inspire and guide concrete legal evolutions. This piece proposes both a methodological argument on how to make room for the contributions made by ethical theory within a legal argument and an exemplification of this innovative approach as a way to uncover new research fields for both immigration law and ethics. This legal turn represents a promising development of the consistency-based approach used widely by philosophers arguing from the point of view of liberal and democratic values and highlighting inconsistency in immigration policy. The legal turn pleads for a new locus for ethical investigation (namely immigration law) and proposes a methodology labelled as a ‘normative reflexive dialogue’. The potential of this dialogue will be exemplified through the principle of proportionality, a decisive principle for migration law and ethics. Johan Rochel Copyright (c) 2017 Rochel https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0 2017-06-14 2017-06-14 7 4 31 55 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.174131 A Puzzle about Obscenity https://de-ethica.com/article/view/1778 Laws against sexual obscenity rely on a distinction between explicit materials that merely offend and materials that cause something worse than offense. While most offensive content is protected under the banner of freedom of expression, obscenity is not. In this paper I try to locate a distinctive harm in the case of obscenity, that would justify prohibiting this material while permitting other kinds of offensive content. I argue that the best case for laws against obscenity relies on the concept of moral harm. If we rely on Mill’s Harm Principle and moral harm is a real harm, then it could be used to justify the distinction between protected and unprotected sexually explicit speech. I argue this demonstrates a weakness in the Harm Principle as a liberal principle of justice. By giving weight to moral harm, Mill’s principle risks eroding an important distinction between the public and private domains. Michael Joel Kessler Copyright (c) 2017 Kessler https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0 2017-06-14 2017-06-14 7 4 5 30 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.17415 From the Editors: De Ethica. A Journal of Philosophical, Theological and Applied Ethics (German) https://de-ethica.com/article/view/1777 <p>No abstract available.</p> Jenny Ehnberg Copyright (c) 2017 https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0 2017-06-14 2017-06-14 7 4 3 4 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.17413 From the Editors: De Ethica. A Journal of Philosophical, Theological and Applied Ethics (English) https://de-ethica.com/article/view/1776 <p>No abstract available.</p> Jenny Ehnberg Copyright (c) 2017 https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0 2017-06-14 2017-06-14 7 4 1 2 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.17411 Ecological Limits and the Meaning of Freedom: A Defense of Liberty as Non-Domination https://de-ethica.com/article/view/1775 It is now widely acknowledged that global environmental problems raise pressing social and political issues, but relatively little philosophical attention has been paid to their bearing on the concept of liberty. This must surprise us, because the question of whether environmental policies are at odds with individual liberty is bound to be controversial in the political arena. First, this article explains why a thorough philosophical debate about the relation between liberty and environmental constraints is needed. Second, based on Philip Pettit’s typology of liberty, it assesses how different conceptions of liberty fare in a context of stringent ecological limits. Indeed, a simple conceptual analysis shows that some conceptions of liberty are more compatible than others with such limits, and with the policies necessary to avoid overshooting them. The article concludes that Pettit’s conception of liberty as non-domination is more compatible with the existence of stringent ecological limits than the two alternatives considered. Augustin Fragnière Copyright (c) 2016 Fragnière https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0 2017-02-02 2017-02-02 7 4 33 49 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.163333 Transworld Egoism, Empathy, and the Golden Rule https://de-ethica.com/article/view/1774 According to preferentism, the ‘desire theory’ of well-being, one is made better off to the extent that her preferences, or desires, are satisfied. According to narrow preferentism, preferentism as it has traditionally been understood, the preferences that matter in this regard are just actual preferences; preferences we might ‘easily have had’, do not matter. On this account also, only actual preference satisfaction contributes to well-being. Merely possible preference satisfaction, including the ‘real possibility’ of attaining desired states of affairs, does not contribute to well-being. Broad preferentism makes sense of the intuition that feasibility as such contributes to well-being. On this account, we are made better off not only by the actual satisfaction of our actual preferences but also by the mere feasibility of satisfying preferences that we ‘might easily have had’. In addition to making sense of our intuition that feasibility as such, contributes to our well-being, broad preferentism provides a rationale for altruistic behavior. On this account support policies that benefit worldmates whose actual circumstances are different from our own because their circumstances are the our circumstances at nearby possible worlds, and our circumstances at other possible worlds, affect our own actual well-being. Harriet E. Baber Copyright (c) 2016 Baber https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0 2017-02-02 2017-02-02 7 4 21 31 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.163321 Utilitarianism and Animal Cruelty: Further Doubts https://de-ethica.com/article/view/1773 Utilitarianism has an apparent pedigree when it comes to animal welfare. It supports the view that animal welfare matters just as much as human welfare. And many utilitarians support and oppose various practices in line with more mainstream concern over animal welfare, such as that we should not kill animals for food or other uses, and that we ought not to torture animals for fun. This relationship has come under tension from many directions. The aim of this article is to add further considerations in support of that tension. I suggest three ways in which utilitarianism comes significantly apart from mainstream concerns with animal welfare. First, utilitarianism opposes animal cruelty only when it offers an inefficient ratio of pleasure to pain; while this may be true of eating animal products, it is not obviously true of other abuses. Second, utilitarianism faces a familiar problem of the inefficacy of individual decisions; I consider a common response to this worry, and offer further concerns. Finally, the common utilitarian argument against animal cruelty ignores various pleasures that humans may get from the superior status that a structure supporting exploitation confers. Ben Davies Copyright (c) 2016 Davies https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0 2017-02-02 2017-02-02 7 4 5 19 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.16335 From the Editors (German) https://de-ethica.com/article/view/1772 <p>Abstract not available.</p> Maren Behrensen Copyright (c) 2016 Behrensen https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0 2017-02-02 2017-02-02 7 4 3 4 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.16333 From the Editors (English) https://de-ethica.com/article/view/1771 <p>Abstract not available.</p> Maren Behrensen Copyright (c) 2016 Behrensen https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0 2017-02-02 2017-02-02 7 4 1 2 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.16331 From the Editors (English) https://de-ethica.com/article/view/1765 <p>No abstract available.</p> Marcus Agnafors Copyright (c) 2016 Agnafors https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0 2016-08-17 2016-08-17 7 4 1 2 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.16321 From the Editors (German) https://de-ethica.com/article/view/1766 <p>No abstract available.</p> Marcus Agnafors Copyright (c) 2016 Agnafors https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0 2016-08-17 2016-08-17 7 4 3 4 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.16323 Run the Experiment, Publish the Study, Close the Sale: Business, Values, Science and Biomedical Research – A Thematic Introduction https://de-ethica.com/article/view/1767 Business models for biomedical research prescribe decentralization due to market selection pressures. I argue that decentralized biomedical research does not match four normative philosophical models of the role of values in science. Non-epistemic values affect the internal stages of for-profit biomedical science. Publication planning, effected by Contract Research Organizations, inhibits mechanisms for transformative criticism. The structure of contracted research precludes attribution of responsibility for foreseeable harm resulting from methodological choices. The effectiveness of business strategies leads to over-representation of profit values versus the values of the general public. These disconnects in respect to the proper role of values in science results from structural issues ultimately linked to the distinct goals of business versus applied science, and so it seems likely that disconnects will also be found in other dimensions of attempts to combine business and science. The volume and integration in the publishing community of decentralized biomedical research imply that the entire community of biomedical research science cannot match the normative criteria of community-focused models of values in science. Several proposals for changing research funding structure might successfully relieve market pressures that drive decentralization. Aleta Quinn Copyright (c) 2016 Quinn https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0 2016-08-17 2016-08-17 7 4 5 21 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.16325 The Good Bishop and the Explanation of Political Authority https://de-ethica.com/article/view/1768 A central problem of political philosophy is that of explaining how a state could have the moral authority to enforce laws, promulgate laws which citizens are thereby obliged to obey, give new duties to citizens and levy taxes. Many rival solutions to this problem of political authority have been offered by contemporary and recent philosophers but none has obtained wide acceptance. The current debate takes no cognisance of George Berkeley’s ‘Passive Obedience’, in which he defends the exceptionless duty of not using force to resist the state and offers a rule-consequentialist account of morality which indicates an explanation of political authority as grounded in the social connectedness of human beings. I expound, criticise and develop Berkeley’s explanation to provide a promising solution to the problem of political authority. The solution impugns the political authority of all existing states as well as the duty of passive obedience. Danny Frederick Copyright (c) 2016 Frederick https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0 2016-08-17 2016-08-17 7 4 23 35 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.163223 Catholicism and Cosmopolitanism: the Confluence of Three Catholic Scholars and the Cosmopolitan Democrats on State Sovereignty and the Future of Global Governance https://de-ethica.com/article/view/1769 One of the central questions in international relations today is how we should conceive of state sovereignty. The notion of sovereignty—’supreme authority within a territory’, as Daniel Philpott defines it—emerged after the Treaty of Westphalia in 1648 as a result of which the late medieval crisis of pluralism was settled. But recent changes in the international order, such as technological advances that have spurred globalization and the emerging norm of the Responsibility to Protect, have cast the notion of sovereignty into an unclear light. The purpose of this paper is to contribute to the current debate regarding sovereignty by exploring two schools of thought on the matter: first, three Catholic scholars from the past century—Luigi Sturzo, Jacques Maritain, and John Courtney Murray, S.J.—taken as representative of Catholic tradition; second, a number of contemporary political theorists of cosmopolitan democracy. The paper argues that there is a confluence between the Catholic thinkers and the cosmopolitan democrats regarding their understanding of state sovereignty and that, taken together, the two schools have much to contribute not only to our current understanding of sovereignty, but also to the future of global governance. Matthew Bagot Copyright (c) 2016 Bagot https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0 2016-08-17 2016-08-17 7 4 37 51 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.163237 Should We Ascribe Capabilities to Sentient Animals? A Critical Analysis of the Extension of Nussbaum’s Capabilities Approach https://de-ethica.com/article/view/1770 Originally, the Capabilities Approach had a strong anthropocentric orientation because of its focus on the entitlements of individual humans. However, as a part of the interest to employ it within animal and environmental ethics, it has been discussed whether the Capabilities Approach should consider also non-human life forms for their own sake. The most influential and elaborated contribution to this debate is Martha Nussbaum’s extension of the Capabilities Approach to include sentient animals. In this article, we argue that Nussbaum’s ascription of capabilities to animals is problematic, since the concept of a capability normally denotes an opportunity to choose between different functionings. When Nussbaum ascribes capabilities to animals, the concept seems to simply denote specific abilities. Such a use is problematic since it waters down the concept and makes it less meaningful, and it may obscure the fact that normal, adult humans, in contrast to sentient animals, can act as conscious moral agents. The aim of granting moral status to sentient animals can be achieved more convincingly by describing our moral relationship to animals in terms of the functionings we should promote, instead of ascribing capabilities to them. Originally, the Capabilities Approach had a strong anthropocentric orientation because of its focus on the entitlements of individual humans. However, as a part of the interest to employ it within animal and environmental ethics, it has been discussed whether the Capabilities Approach should consider also non-human life forms for their own sake. The most influential and elaborated contribution to this debate is Martha Nussbaum’s extension of the Capabilities Approach to include sentient animals. In this article, we argue that Nussbaum’s ascription of capabilities to animals is problematic, since the concept of a capability normally denotes an opportunity to choose between different functionings. When Nussbaum ascribes capabilities to animals, the concept seems to simply denote specific abilities. Such a use is problematic since it waters down the concept and makes it less meaningful, and it may obscure the fact that normal, adult humans, in contrast to sentient animals, can act as conscious moral agents. The aim of granting moral status to sentient animals can be achieved more convincingly by describing our moral relationship to animals in terms of the functionings we should promote, instead of ascribing capabilities to them. Anders Melin David Kronlid Copyright (c) 2016 Melin, Kronlid https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0 2016-08-17 2016-08-17 7 4 53 63 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.163253 From the Editors (English) https://de-ethica.com/article/view/1758 <p>No abstract available.</p> Elena Namli Copyright (c) 2016 Namli https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0 2016-05-09 2016-05-09 7 4 1 1 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.16311 From the Editors (German) https://de-ethica.com/article/view/1759 <p>No abstract available.</p> Elena Namli Copyright (c) 2016 Namli https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0 2016-05-09 2016-05-09 7 4 2 3 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.16312 Globalisation and Global Justice - A Thematic Introduction https://de-ethica.com/article/view/1760 Globalisation involves both promising potentials and risks. It has the potential – through the spread of human rights, the migration of people and ideas, and the integration of diverse economies – to improve human wellbeing and enhance the protection of human rights worldwide. But globalisation also incurs risks: global environmental risks (such as global warming), the creation of new centres of power with limited legitimacy, a ‘race to the bottom’ regarding workers’ safety and rights, risky journeys of thousands of migrants and not least growing global inequalities. Globalisation, therefore, is a key factor for today’s discussions of justice. <p>As globalisation connects people, it also raises associated responsibilities between them. Until recently, the interest in justice among political philosophers and social ethicists was mainly focused on the nation state. However, this is no longer feasible. Since economic globalisation affects how wealth and power are distributed globally it has become indispensable to discuss social ethics in a global context and to develop principles of global justice. Global justice, therefore, entails an assessment of the benefits and burdens of the structural relations and institutional arrangements that constitute and govern globalisation.</p> <p>The academic discussion of global justice is vibrant and expanding. In my introduction I provide an overview of the discussions on global poverty, justice, cosmopolitanism and statism, migration, the capability approach and different dimensions of global justice.</p> Göran Collste Copyright (c) 2016 Collste https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0 2016-05-09 2016-05-09 7 4 5 17 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.16315 Does Global Justice Require More than Just Global Institutions? https://de-ethica.com/article/view/1761 The ‘institutional approach’ to justice holds that persons’ responsibility of justice is primarily to support, maintain, and comply with the rules of just institutions. Within the rules of just institutions, so long as their actions do not undermine these background institutions, individuals have no further responsibilities of justice. But what does the institutional approach say in the non-ideal context where just institutions are absent, such as in the global case? One reading of the institutional approach, in this case, is that our duties are primarily to create just institutions, and that when we are doing our part in this respect, we may legitimately pursue other personal or associational ends. This ‘strong’ reading of our institutional duty takes it to be both a necessary and sufficient duty of justice of individuals that they do their part to establish just arrangements. But how plausible is this? On the one hand this requirement seems overly inflexible; on the other it seems overly lax. I clarify the motivation and context of this reading of the institutional duty, and suggest that it need not be as implausible as it seems. Kok-Chor Tan Copyright (c) 2016 Tan https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0 2016-05-09 2016-05-09 7 4 19 31 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.163119 Global Justice in Lutheran Political Theology https://de-ethica.com/article/view/1763 The purpose of this article is to examine the contributions that might be given by Lutheran political theology to the discourse on global justice. The article offers a critical examination of three different theories of global justice within political philosophy. Contractarian theories are criticized, and a thesis is that it is plausible to argue that justice can be understood as liberation from oppression. From this perspective the article gives an analysis of an influential theory of justice within Lutheran ethics. According to this theory justice is not an equal distribution but an arrangement where the subordinate respect the authority of those in power. This theory is related to a sharp distinction between law and gospel. The main thesis of the article is that Lutheran political theology should take a different approach if it aims to give a constructive contribution to theories of justice. This means that Lutheran ethics should not be based on Creation and reason alone – it should also be based on Christology and Eschatology. Carl-Henric Grenholm Copyright (c) 2016 Grenholm https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0 2016-05-09 2016-05-09 7 4 45 58 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.163145 Global Responsibility and the Enhancement of Life https://de-ethica.com/article/view/1762 This article advances a conception of global ethics in terms of the centrality of responsibility to the moral life and also the moral good of the enhancement of life. In contrast to some forms of global ethics, the article also seeks to warrant the use of religious sources in developing such an ethics. Specifically, the article seeks to demonstrate the greater adequacy of a global ethics of responsibility for the enhancement of life against rival conceptions developed in terms of Human Rights discourse or the so-called Capabilities Approach. The article ends with a conception of ‘conscience’ as the mode of human moral being and the experience of religious transcendence within the domains of human social and historical life. From this idea, conscience is specified a human right and capacity to determine the humane use of religious resources and also the norm for the rejection of inhumane expressions of religion within global ethics. William Schweiker Copyright (c) 2016 Schweiker https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0 2016-05-09 2016-05-09 7 4 33 44 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.163133 Talents in the Service of Justice: Responding to Unequal Ownership beyond Compliance https://de-ethica.com/article/view/1764 Over the past few decades, economic inequalities have continued to grow in most countries and the world is still lacking effective global tax schemes or corresponding structures of global distributive justice. Thus, for the world’s top-owners, simply complying with the existing rules hardly suffices as a virtue of justice. In the current article, G. A. Cohen’s nation-centered account of individual virtues in the service of distributive justice is elaborated further in a broader perspective. First, Cohen’s basic insights into the virtues of the talented rich are reconsidered under the conditions of highly unequal Western democracies in the global age as recently depicted by Thomas Piketty. Second, it is asked with reference to the Bill and Melinda Gates Foundation, if the exceptional generosity of some superrich people can serve as a proper response to the assumed deficit of justice. Third, an ethic of generous compliance is outlined as a possible mediating approach in the discussion of the responsibilities of the talented rich in an age of high economic, health, and capability inequalities as well as public sector austerity. Ville Päivänsalo Copyright (c) 2016 Päivänsalo https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0 2016-05-09 2016-05-09 7 4 59 74 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.163159 From the Editors (English) https://de-ethica.com/article/view/1751 <p>Not Available.</p> Elena Namli Copyright (c) 2015 Namli https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0 2016-01-28 2016-01-28 7 4 1 2 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.15231 From the Editors (German) https://de-ethica.com/article/view/1752 <p>Not Available.</p> Elena Namli Copyright (c) 2015 Namli https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0 2016-01-28 2016-01-28 7 4 3 4 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.15233 Introduction. Capitalism: Theological Perspectives and Critiques https://de-ethica.com/article/view/1753 Not Available. Neil Messer Copyright (c) 2015 Messer https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0 2016-01-28 2016-01-28 7 4 5 6 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.15235 ‘Justice and Right’: Biblical Ethics and the Regulation of Capitalism https://de-ethica.com/article/view/1754 The Hebrew expression in the Old Testament mishpat u-tsedaqa, conventionally translated ‘justice and righteousness’, has a particular application to the social responsibility of the king. The state, in the person of the king, is seen in the Old Testament as having an obligation to exercise its power on behalf of the most vulnerable. This may be illustrated by the widespread evidence from the ancient Near East of administrative and judicial action undertaken by kings to cancel debts, provide for the release of debt slaves, remit taxes, order the return of distrained property, and so forth. Although the impact of such measures would have been limited, and the tradition is attenuated in later levels of the text, the ideal of the state as the protector of the poor may be applied to the state’s relationship with the modern capitalist economy. It demands that the economy should be regulated to protect the most vulnerable against the impoverishment resulting from its transformation by globalized capitalism. The reality, however, especially in the UK and the US, is that the state colludes with capitalism to increase inequality and deepen poverty. Walter Houston Copyright (c) 2015 Houston https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0 2016-01-28 2016-01-28 7 4 7 21 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.15237 Ireland, Rent, and the Theologies of Real Estate https://de-ethica.com/article/view/1755 In this paper, taking the Irish economic crash of 2008 as the starting point, a theological response to real estate speculation is considered. By analysing the ways in which property development was a key factor in the collapse of the Irish economy, the flaws of such markets in crisis are exposed. Yet ethical concerns persist even when real estate markets are stable. Drawing on the Christian tradition around usury, an argument is made that an appropriate ecclesial reaction to the problems created by economies largely driven by real estate speculation involves developing alternative modes of conceiving land and economy. By drawing on the Vineyard song of Isaiah 5, a claim is made that faithful Christian practice demands a response of economic experimentation around property driven by a telos other than profit. Kevin Hargaden Copyright (c) 2015 Hargaden https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0 2016-01-28 2016-01-28 7 4 23 38 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.152323 Time for Business: Business Ethics, Sustainability, and Giorgio Agamben’s ‘Messianic Time’ https://de-ethica.com/article/view/1756 Contemporary business continues to intensify its radical relation to time. The New York Stock Exchange recently announced that in pursuing (as traders call it) the ‘race to zero’ they will begin using laser technology originally developed for military communications to send information about trades nearly at the speed of light. This is just one example of short-term temporal rhythms embedded in the practices of contemporary firms which watch their stock price on an hourly basis, report their earnings quarterly, and dissolve future consequences and costs through discounting procedures. There is reason to believe that these radical conceptions of time and its passing impair the ability of businesses to function in a morally coherent manner. In the spirit of other recent critiques of modern temporality such as David Couzen Hoys The Time of Our Lives, in this paper, I present a critique of the temporality of modern business. In response, I assess the recent attempt to provide an alternative account of temporality using theological concepts by Giorgio Agamben. I argue that Agamben’s more integrative account of messianic time provides a richer ambitemporal account which might provide a viable temporality for a new sustainable economic future. Jeremy Kidwell Copyright (c) 2015 Kidwell https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0 2016-01-28 2016-01-28 7 4 39 51 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.152339 The Rise of Religion and the Future of Capitalism https://de-ethica.com/article/view/1757 The rise of religion and the rise of capitalism are currently occurring in roughly the same geographical regions (Latin America, Asia, and Africa). Although both religion and capitalism are often ignored, or are regarded negatively, within development circles, this article reflects on their potential for human wellbeing when they convergence. Its focus is on the socio-economic significance of what the author calls the Evangelical Pentecostal Charismatic Movement (EPCM), which accounts for most of the growth of Christianity, the world’s largest religion. He argues that the movement’s stimulation of selfempowerment (especially of women), church-based social outreach, and the encouragement of trust are of particular significance. They provide ample grounds, he contends, for revisiting the question Max Weber is famous for having posed about the link between religious belief and economic behaviour. They also help overcome victimhood mentalities and promote good stewardship, accountability and integrity. The EPCM thereby acts as a progressive force that, in serving the common good, stands to make a positive contribution to the future of capitalism. Peter S. Heslam Copyright (c) 2015 Heslam https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0 2016-01-28 2016-01-28 7 4 53 72 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.152353 The Scope of the Global Institutional Order: Can Pogge Survive Cohen’s Critique of Rawls? https://de-ethica.com/article/view/1750 In this paper, I develop a critique of Thomas Pogge&#8221;s attempt in Realizing Rawls to expand the scope of the Original Position. I argue that Pogge is guilty of assuming the same arbitrary boundary between public and private behaviours made by Rawls. To actualize this critique, I take G. A. Cohen&#8217;s critique of John Rawls, found in its fullest form in Rescuing Justice and Equality, alongside Thomas Pogge&#8221;s attempt, in Realizing Rawls, to expand the scope of the Original Position. Cohen argues that the boundary Rawls wishes to draw between the public and private cannot be coherently maintained in the application of the Difference Principle. I argue that if this claim is true, then Pogge&#8221;s attempt to expand the scope of Rawls&#8221; Theory of Justice to the international arena is actually considerably more radical than Pogge intended. Not only do we need to worry about the justice of institutions in international law, but we now need to worry about the justice of individual actions inside a system of global justice. I conclude by considering some objections against Cohen&#8221;s, and thus, my position. Kevin W. Gray Copyright (c) 2015 Gray https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0 2015-09-28 2015-09-28 7 4 19 34 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.152223 Trolleys and Transplants: Derailing the Distinction Between Doing and Allowing https://de-ethica.com/article/view/1749 Two key elements in Judith Jarvis Thomson&#8217;s most recent response to the famed Trolley Problem produce a tension that threatens to undermine her account. First, in a reversal of part of her 1985 position, Thomson now argues that a bystander is not permitted to divert a threat. Second, her use of the Doctrine of Doing and Allowing (DDA) to explain intuitions about the permissibility of threat diversion conflicts with her constraint of an agent&#8217;s available options to the present tense, which is designed to prevent past bad acts from justifying bad acts in the present. I contend that the conflict between DDA and the tense constraint creates an inconsistency in Thomson&#8217;s current position and supports the conclusion that no one, including the trolley driver, is permitted to turn the trolley. In order to resolve this conflict, Thomson must either abandon one of the core features of her explanation or reject a fundamental intuition driving the Trolley Problem, that the driver may divert the trolley to save lives. Emma Duncan Copyright (c) 2015 Duncan https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0 2015-09-28 2015-09-28 7 4 9 18 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.15229 From the Editors (GER): De Ethica. A Journal of Philosophical, Theological and Applied Ethics https://de-ethica.com/article/view/1748 <p>No abstract available.</p> Marcus Agnafors Copyright (c) 2015 Agnafors https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0 2015-09-28 2015-09-28 7 4 5 7 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.15225 From the Editors (ENG): De Ethica. A Journal of Philosophical, Theological and Applied Ethics https://de-ethica.com/article/view/1747 <p>No abstract available.</p> Marcus Agnafors Copyright (c) 2015 Agnafors https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0 2015-09-28 2015-09-28 7 4 1 3 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.15221 From the Editors (English) https://de-ethica.com/article/view/1741 <p>No abstract available.</p> Maren Behrensen Copyright (c) 2015 Behrensen https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0 2015-05-05 2015-05-05 7 4 1 2 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.15211 From the Editors (German) https://de-ethica.com/article/view/1742 <p>No abstract available.</p> Maren Behrensen Copyright (c) 2015 Behrensen https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0 2015-05-05 2015-05-05 7 4 3 4 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.15213 Humanitarian Intervention and Moral Responsibility https://de-ethica.com/article/view/1744 This essay investigates the moral aspects of humanitarian intervention. Humanitarian intervention involves the balancing of at least three sometimes contradictory principles – the autonomy of states, the prohibition of war and the reduction of harm and human suffering – and hence requires not merely a legal and political approach to the matter but renders a moral viewpoint necessary. It is argued that P.F. Strawson&#8217;s concept Moral Reactive Attitudes MRA) contributes to analysing the moral dilemmas and priorities involved. First, MRA underlines the moral aspects of international society that are essential for dealing with the moral conflict inherent in international society. Secondly, MRA helps to balance between competing claims of justification and legitimacy in cases of humanitarian intervention. Ronnie Hjorth Copyright (c) 2015 Hjorth https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0 2015-05-05 2015-05-05 7 4 19 34 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.152119 An Ethical Outlook on The Influence of Memory on Violence https://de-ethica.com/article/view/1745 As we witness the growing popularity of what it referred to as memory discourse within the fields of historical and cultural studies, it becomes apparent that there is a lack of systematic insight into the ethical dimension of this subject. This paper attempts to alleviate this imbalance. In the first section, the author scrutinizes the relationship between memory and violence. This has appeared in human history as a very real and multifaceted issue but remains under-explored in philosophy and theology. Given the vibrant nature and moral fickleness of memory, in the second section, the author outlines some ethical requirements that should regulate the use of memory. Epistemological, pedagogical and practical aspects of memory are taken into consideration within a comprehensive, broader social context, as well as individual demands. Presuming that memory can be a valuable ingredient for a good life, the author reconsiders the ethical criteria for memory, which should not just prevent violence but also stimulate tolerance and cohabitation. Jasna Čurkovi č Nimac Copyright (c) 2015 ?urkovi ? Nimac https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0 2015-05-05 2015-05-05 7 4 35 48 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.152135 Targeted and Non-targeted Killing https://de-ethica.com/article/view/1746 After some historical remarks about former examples of Targeted killing the paper asks about the paradigm in which targeted killing could fit: punishment, police action, war of which the latter one seems to be the most promising. In this context, the problem of Immunity of non-combatants and who is to be counted as such becomes relevant. Werner Wolbert Copyright (c) 2015 Wolbert https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0 2015-05-05 2015-05-05 7 4 49 60 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.152149 In Defence of Just War: Christian Tradition, Controversies, and Cases https://de-ethica.com/article/view/1743 This article presents four controversial issues that are raised by the articulation of just war thinking in my book, In Defence of War (2013, 2014): the conception of just war as punitive, the penultimate nature of the authority of international law, the morality of national interest, and the elasticity of the requirement of proportionality. It then proceeds to illustrate the interpretation of some of the criteria of just war in terms of three topical cases: Britain&#8217;s belligerency against Germany in 1914, the Syrian rebellion against the Assad regime in 2011, and Israe&#8217;s Operation Protective Edge against Hamas in Gaza in 2013. It is often claimed that just war thinking has been rendered obsolete by novel phenomena such as nuclear weapons, wars &#8216;among the people&#8217;, war-by-remote-control, and cyber-aggression. The presentation of issues and cases in this article, notwithstanding its brevity, is sufficient to show that just war thinking continues to develop by wrestling with controversial conceptual problems and thinking its way through novel sets of circumstances. Nigel Biggar Copyright (c) 2015 Biggar https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0 2015-05-05 2015-05-05 7 4 5 17 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.15215 From the Editors (English) https://de-ethica.com/article/view/1736 <p>No abstract available.</p> Marcus Agnafors Copyright (c) 2014 Marcus Agnafors https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0 2014-12-16 2014-12-16 7 4 1 2 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.14131 From the Editors (German) https://de-ethica.com/article/view/1737 <p>No abstract available.</p> Marcus Agnafors Copyright (c) 2014 Marcus Agnafors https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0 2014-12-16 2014-12-16 7 4 3 4 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.14133 Shaky Ground https://de-ethica.com/article/view/1738 The debate surrounding free will and moral responsibility is one of the most intransigent debates in contemporary philosophy - but it does not have to be. At its heart, the free will debate is a metaethical debate - a debate about the meaning of certain moral terms - free will, moral responsibility, blameworthiness, praiseworthiness. Compatibilists argue that these concepts are compatible with wholly deterministic world, while incompatibilists argue that these concepts require indeterminism, or multiple possible futures. However, compatibilists and incompatibilists do not disagree on everything - both parties agree that free will and moral responsibility require control - the kind of control that we believe we have over the majority of our everyday actions. Over the course of any given day each of us makes countless choices, and in most situations as we make these choices we cannot help but believe that we are in control of them - that our actions are free and we are morally responsible for them. Here I argue that our concepts of free will and moral responsibility are inexorably tied to this experience of apparent liberty. William Simkulet Copyright (c) 2014 William Simkulet https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0 2014-12-16 2014-12-16 7 4 5 18 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.14135 Climate Migration and the State’s Duty to Protect https://de-ethica.com/article/view/1739 Climate change will have as a consequence a more or less important rise of global sea levels. For some countries, this is likely to mean their total disappearance, if no measures are taken. Some of these measures might be too costly for the country to finance and its population will have no other choice but to migrate to another country. This contribution considers this kind of problem from the point of view of political philosophy. My arguments will rest on two fundamental assumptions. On the one hand, we find the state&#8217;s duty to protect its citizens against internal and external dangers, and on the other, the individual&#8217;s right not to have to migrate. Each state must protect its own citizens against foreign dangers. It will also be assumed that no state has a right to endanger the very existence of another state. The contribution aims to show some of the major consequences of these assumptions for the ethical problem of migration due to the consequences of human-induced climate change. Norbert Campagna Copyright (c) 2014 Norbert Campagna https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0 2014-12-16 2014-12-16 7 4 19 34 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.141319 Enhancing Humans and Sustainability: The Reunion of Bioethics and Environmental Ethics https://de-ethica.com/article/view/1740 Emerging technologies are hyped as &#8216;transformative&#8217; by their proponents, who prophesize that these new technologies will significantly and beneficially change our world. Concerns have been raised about the potential environmental impacts of these technologies. Emerging technologies and their implications on humans, society, and the environment challenge our understanding of our responsibilities to the environment and future generations. Utilizing Van Potter&#8217;s sense of bioethics that meant the normative study of humanity&#8217;s place in the biosphere, I attempt to reintegrate bioethics and environmental ethics, to address questions about human well-being in the future, its dependence on complex environmental systems, and the impact of emerging technologies particularly enhancement technologies upon it. Ultimately, I argue that the future envisioned by proponents of human enhancement technologies is not consistent with our responsibilities to future generations which including leaving certain amounts of natural capital, including human ones. Joan McGregor Copyright (c) 2014 Joan McGregor https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0 2014-12-16 2014-12-16 7 4 35 53 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.141335 From the Editors: De Ethica. A Journal of Philosophical, Theological and Applied Ethics (English) https://de-ethica.com/article/view/1730 <p>No abstract available.</p> Maren Behrensen Copyright (c) 2014 Maren Behrensen https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0 2014-08-21 2014-08-21 7 4 1 2 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.14121 From the Editors: De Ethica. A Journal of Philosophical, Theological and Applied Ethics (German) https://de-ethica.com/article/view/1731 <p>No abstract available.</p> Maren Behrensen Copyright (c) 2014 Maren Behrensen https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0 2014-08-21 2014-08-21 7 4 3 4 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.14123 Environmental Ethics as a Question of Environmental Ontology: Naess’ Ecosophy T and Buddhist Traditions https://de-ethica.com/article/view/1733 Arne Naess included several references to Buddhist teachings in his ecophilosophy. I suggest an inquiry into and interpretation of the Buddhist sources of Naess&#8217; proposal, in order to understand the role Buddhist elements play in it, and how they can offer a further understanding of central elements in Naess&#8217; ecosophy. The focus is on the union of theory, worldview and practice, which lies at the core of both fields. A particular emphasis is placed on the idea that only a change of outlook on the nature of reality can promote an ethical transformation. In Naess&#8217; approach, the ecological crisis is first of all a problem of our experience of the world, posing a question of &#8216;environmental ontology&#8217;. I suggest an hermeneutical approach primarily into early Indian Buddhist sources, and I argue that although a homogeneous &#8216;Buddhism&#8217;, as well as a &#8216;green Buddhism&#8217; are problematic, different strands of thinking in Buddhist philosophy can facilitate the analysis of critical points also raised by Ecosophy T, supporting and expanding an ecosophical approach to ecological challenges. Elisa Cavazza Copyright (c) 2014 Elisa Cavazza https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0 2014-08-21 2014-08-21 7 4 23 48 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.141223 Do No Harm: A Cross-Disciplinary, Cross-Cultural Climate Ethics https://de-ethica.com/article/view/1732 Anthropogenic climate change has become a hot button issue in the scientific, economic, political, and ethical sectors. While the science behind climate change is clear, responses in the economic and political realms have been unfulfilling. On the economic front, companies have marketed themselves as pioneers in the quest to go green while simultaneously engaging in environmentally destructive practices and on the political front, politicians have failed to make any significant global progress. I argue that climate change needs to be framed as an ethical issue to make serious progress towards the path to a sustainable human civilization. In an effort to motivate the urgency needed to confront climate change, I argue that climate change seriously affects human beings living here and now, and if one cares about unnecessarily harming fellow innocent living human beings, then one should care about one&#8217;s own environmental impact related to climate change. Since this argument does not depend upon any specific philosophical, religious, or ethical tradition but applies regardless of one&#8217;s particular background, I hope to induce genuine concern among all human beings regarding this issue. Casey Rentmeester Copyright (c) 2014 Casey Rentmeester https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0 2014-08-21 2014-08-21 7 4 5 21 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.14125 From the Editors: De Ethica. A Journal of Philosophical, Theological and Applied Ethics (German) https://de-ethica.com/article/view/1724 <p>No abstract available.</p> Brenda Almond Copyright (c) 2014 Brenda Almond https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0 2014-03-31 2014-03-31 7 4 5 7 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.14115 Climate Change and Responsibility to Future Generations: Reflections on the Normative Questions https://de-ethica.com/article/view/1725 Climate change raises in an important way the problem of moral responsibility. It forces us to recognise that we have a responsibility to future generations, and to ask what this responsibility implies. Here I identify four key normative questions: (1) How should we respond to uncertainty? Should we apply cost-benefit analysis in order to cope with uncertainty? (2) How should we evaluate the emission of greenhouse gases? Given that the effects of emissions will be bad, should we judge that we as emitters harm the receivers and by that do them an injustice? (3) How should we compare present costs and future benefits? Should we give little or much weight to the benefits and well-being of people in the further future? (4) How should we take heed of human rights? Should we try to avoid the adverse outcomes of a cost-benefit approach by adopting a human rights approach that specifies minimum thresholds to which all human beings are entitled? Robert Heeger Copyright (c) 2014 Robert Heeger https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0 2014-03-31 2014-03-31 7 4 9 16 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.14119 An Ethics of Sustainability and Jewish Law? https://de-ethica.com/article/view/1726 This article addresses the issue of why it is important to ask for ethical responses to questions of sustainability and an ethics of an open future, and why the technocratic approach as practiced in most Western countries might not be sustainable. Second, it examines what a religious perspective has to offer for the discourse. In particular, this is the perspective of Jewish Law (halakhah); today a mere niche subject, a law system without territory and primarily based on the tradition of a religious minority. It is argued that despite these facts the Jewish legal system should be taken into account, as it offers a rich and unique tradition of more than 3,000 years of discussion and thought that still provides revealing insights. Two Jewish legal principles, bal tashchit and migrash exemplify this claim, before an outlook on possible contributions is given. Jann Reinhardt Copyright (c) 2014 Jann Reinhardt https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0 2014-03-31 2014-03-31 7 4 17 35 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.141117 Climate Change, Human Rights and the Problem of Motivation https://de-ethica.com/article/view/1727 In this paper, I discuss some of the human rights that are threatened by the impact of global warming and the problem of motivation to comply with the duties of climate justice. I explain in what sense human rights can be violated by climate change and try to show that there are not only moral reasons to address this problem, but also more prudential motives, which I refer to as quasi-moral and non-moral reasons. I also assess some implications of potentially catastrophic impacts driven by this ecological issue. My aim is to locate, by outlining a normative perspective based on sound empirical findings, urgent climate injustices, and explain why well-off citizens in developed countries have strong reasons to avert the potentially massive violation of the rights of present and future victims of climate change. Michel Bourban Copyright (c) 2014 Michel Bourban https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0 2014-03-31 2014-03-31 7 4 37 52 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.141137 Understanding Climate Change as an Existential Threat: Confronting Climate Denial as a Challenge to Climate Ethics https://de-ethica.com/article/view/1728 Climate change cannot be managed by experts and politicians alone. Consequently, climate ethics must take up the challenge of inviting public responsibility on this issue. New sociological research on climate denial by Kari Norgaard, however, suggests that most citizens of industrialized countries are ill-prepared to cope with the ethical significance of climate change. I draw upon Martin Heidegger to offer a new reading of climate denial that suggests viable responses to this problem. I argue that the implications of climate change are largely received as an &#8216;existential threat&#8217; to the extent that they endanger the integrity of everyday existence. In other words, the implications of climate change for everyday life unsettle what phenomenologists call the &#8216;lifeworld&#8217;. Should basic lifeworld assumptions, which cultures rely on to makes sense of the world and their purposes in it, come under serious question, anxieties surface that most people are profoundly motivated to avoid. Hence, the ethical obligations entailed by climate change are &#8216;denied&#8217; in the form of protecting lifeworld integrity for the sake of containing anxieties that would otherwise overwhelm people. Finally, I submit that existential approaches to climate denial can empower a confrontation with &#8216;climate anxiety&#8217; in ways that open up ethical reflection. Tim Christion Myers Copyright (c) 2014 Tim Christion Myers https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0 2014-03-31 2014-03-31 7 4 53 70 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.141153 From the Editors: De Ethica. A Journal of Philosophical, Theological and Applied Ethics (English) https://de-ethica.com/article/view/1723 <p>No abstract available.</p> Brenda Almond Copyright (c) 2014 Brenda Almond https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0 2014-03-31 2014-03-31 7 4 1 3 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.14111 An Interview with Professor Simon Caney https://de-ethica.com/article/view/1729 <p>No abstract available.</p> Eric Brandstedt Copyright (c) 2014 Eric Brandstedt https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0 2014-03-31 2014-03-31 7 4 71 84 10.3384/de-ethica.2001-8819.141171